Commutative Algebra 51

Limits Are Left-Exact

By example 6 and proposition 2 in the previous article, one is inclined to conclude that taking the colimit in \mathcal C = A\text{-}\mathbf{Mod} is a right-exact functor, but there is a rather huge issue here: the functors are between \mathcal C and \mathcal D = \mathcal C^J, the category of diagrams in \mathcal C while we only defined exactness of functors between categories of modules. The proper way to do this is to introduce the framework of abelian categories and extend our concept of additive functors and exact functors there. However, doing this will take us too far afield so we will prove it directly (which is, admittedly, a bit of a cop out).

Proposition 1.

Let J be an index category, and D', D, D'' : J\to A\text{-}\mathbf{Mod} be diagrams of type J. For concreteness, write these diagrams as

((N_i), (\beta_e^N : N_i \to N_j)), \ ((M_i), (\beta_e^M : M_i \to M_j)),\ ((P_i), (\beta_e^P : P_i \to P_j))

where i\in J and e:i\to j. Let D'\to D \to D'' be morphisms, written as a collection of N_i\stackrel {\phi_i} \to M_i \stackrel {\psi_i} \to P_i over i\in J. Then

\left( \begin{aligned}0\to N_i\stackrel {\phi_i} \to M_i \stackrel {\psi_i} \to P_i\\ \text{exact for each } i\in J\end{aligned}\right) \implies 0 \to \lim N_i \to \lim M_i \to \lim P_i \text{ exact.}

\left( \begin{aligned}N_i\stackrel {\phi_i} \to M_i \stackrel {\psi_i} \to P_i \to 0\\ \text{exact for each } i\in J\end{aligned}\right) \implies \mathrm{colim} N_i \to \mathrm{colim} M_i \to \mathrm{colim} P_i \to 0\text{ exact.}

Note

In summary, taking the limit is left-exact while taking the colimit is right-exact.

Proof

We prove the second claim, leaving the first as an exercise. By proposition 1 here, \mathrm{colim} M_i is concretely described as follows. Take the quotient of \oplus_{i\in J} M_i by all m_i - \beta_e^M(m_i), where e:i\to j is an arrow in J, m_i \in M_i and \beta_e^M(m_i)\in M_j are identified with their images in \oplus_i M_i.

With this description, clearly \mathrm{colim} M_i \to \mathrm{colim} P_i is surjective. Also, composing \mathrm{colim} N_i \to \mathrm{colim} M_i \to \mathrm{colim} P_i is the zero map so \mathrm{im}(\mathrm{colim} \phi_i) \subseteq \mathrm{ker}(\mathrm{colim} \psi_i). Now write \phi : \oplus_i N_i \to \oplus_i M_i for \oplus \phi_i and \psi : \oplus_i M_i \to \oplus_i P_i for \oplus \psi_i.

Conversely, let x\in \oplus_i M_i represent an element in the kernel of \mathrm{colim} \psi_i. Thus \psi(x) \in\oplus_i P_i is a finite sum of p_i - \beta_e^P(p_i). Since \psi_i is surjective, we can write such a term as

\psi_i(m_i') - \beta_e^P(\psi_i(m_i')) = \psi_i(m_i') - \psi_j(\beta_e^M(m_i')) = \psi(m_i' - \beta_e^M(m_i'))

for some m_i'\in M_i. Since \psi(x) is a finite sum of \psi(m_i' - \beta_e^M(m_i')), we can replace x by another representative such that \psi(x) = 0. Then x = \phi(y) for some y\in \oplus N_i. ♦

warningNeither the limit nor the colimit functor is exact in general. For the colimit case, consider the following commutative diagram of A-modules

pushout_counterexample

where all maps A\to A are identities. The rows are short exact sequences and the squares all commute, but taking the colimit of the columns gives

0 \longrightarrow A^2 \longrightarrow A \longrightarrow 0 \longrightarrow 0

which is not exact.

Exercise A

Find an example for the case of limits.

blue-lin

Direct Limits

We will describe a special case where taking the colimit is exact.

Given a poset (S, \le), we recall the category \mathcal C(S) whose objects are elements of S, and between any x,y\in S, |\mathrm{hom}(x, y)| \le 1 with equality if and only if x \le y. Composition is the obvious one.

Definition.

A poset (S, \le) is called a directed set if for any a,b\in S, there is a c\in S such that a\le c and b\le c.

In other words, a poset is directed if every finite set has an upper bound.

Definition.

If J is an index category obtained from \mathcal C(S) for some directed set S, then a diagram in \mathcal C of type J is called a directed system. The colimit of (A_i)_{i\in J} is called the direct limit and denoted by

\varinjlim_{i\in J} A_i.

In other words, direct limit = colimit over directed set. We will abuse notation a little and regard J as the directed set itself.

To avoid set-theoretic difficulties, the directed set J is always assumed to be non-empty.

Example

In exercise C.3 here, for a multiplicative S\subseteq A and A-module M, we have an isomorphism of A-modules

\mathrm{colim}_{f\in S} M_f \cong M_S

where f\le g if g is a multiple of f. Since S is multiplicative, any {fg} has an upper bound fg. Hence M_S is the direct limit of M_f over f\in S:

\varinjlim_{f\in S} M_f \cong M_S.

Similarly, we have the following direct limit in the category of rings:

\varinjlim_{f\in S} A_f \cong A_S.

Next we will discuss the general direct limit in the categories A-Mod and Ring.

blue-lin

Direct Limit of Modules

Let A be a fixed ring; the following holds for direct limits in the category of A-modules.

Proposition 2.

Suppose ((M_i)_{i\in J}, (\beta_{ij})_{i\le j}) is a directed system of A-modules over a directed set J. Let

M = \varinjlim_{i\in J} M_i, with canonical \epsilon_i : M_i \to M for each i\in J.

Then for each m\in M, there exists an i\in J and m_i \in M_i such that \epsilon_i(m_i) = m.

Also if m_i\in M_i satisfies \epsilon_i(m_i) = 0, then there exists j\ge i such that \beta_{ij}(m_i) = 0 \in M_j.

Note

The philosophy is that “whatever happens in the direct limit happens in M_j for some sufficiently large index j“.

Proof

By proposition 1 here, the colimit M is described concretely by taking the quotient of P = \oplus_{i\in J} M_i (with canonical \nu_i : M_i \to P) by relations of the form

\nu_k(m_k) - \nu_l\beta_{kl}(m_k),\ m_k \in M_i,\ k\le l\ (k, l\in J).

Hence any m\in M can be written as \epsilon_{i_1}(m_1) + \ldots + \epsilon_{i_N}(m_N) for m_1 \in M_{i_1}, \ldots, m_N \in M_{i_N}. But J is a directed set, so we can pick index j\in J such that j\ge i_1, \ldots, i_N; then

m = \epsilon_j(m_j), where m_j = \beta_{i_1 k}(m_1) + \ldots + \beta_{i_N k}(m_N),

proving the first claim.

For the second claim, if \epsilon_i(m_i) = 0 then \nu_i(m_i) \in \oplus_i M_i is a finite sum of the above relations. Pick an index j\in J larger than i and all indices kl in the sum; then \beta_{ij}(m_i) is the sum of the images of these relations in M_k. But each such relation has image \beta_{kj}(m_k) - \beta_{lj}\beta_{kl}(m_k) = 0 in M_k, so \beta_{ij}(m_i) = 0 as desired. ♦

Corollary 1.

If ((M_i), (\beta_{ij})) is a directed system of A-modules such that \beta_{ij} are all injective, then

\epsilon_j : M_j \longrightarrow \varinjlim_i M_i

is also injective for each j\in J.

Finally we have:

Proposition 3.

Let ((M_i), (\beta_{ij})) and ((N_i), (\gamma_{ij})) be directed systems of A-modules and \phi_i : M_i \to N_i be a morphism of the directed systems, i.e. for any i\le j, we have \gamma_{ij} \circ \phi_i = \phi_j \circ \beta_{ij} : M_i \to N_j.

If each \phi_i is injective, so is \phi : \varinjlim M_i \to \varinjlim N_i.

Since taking the colimit is right-exact by proposition 1, we see that taking the direct limit is exact. 

Proof

Write \epsilon_i^M : M_i \to \varinjlim M_i and \epsilon_i^N : N_i \to \varinjlim N_i for the canonical maps.

Suppose \phi(m) = 0 for m \in \varinjlim M_i. By proposition 2, we have m = \epsilon_i^M(m_i) for some m_i \in M_i; then

0 = \phi(m) = \phi(\epsilon_i^M(m_i)) = \epsilon_i^N(\phi_i(m_i))

so by proposition 2 again, there exists j\ge i such that \gamma_{ij}(\phi_i(m_i)) = 0, so \phi_j(\beta_{ij}(m_i)) = 0. Since \phi_j is injective we have \beta_{ij}(m_i) = 0 so m =  \epsilon_i^M(m_i) = \epsilon_j^M\beta_{ij}(m_i) = 0. ♦

Exercise B

Describe the direct limit of sets (S_i) over J. State and prove an analogue of proposition 2.

blue-lin

This entry was posted in Advanced Algebra and tagged , , , , , . Bookmark the permalink.

2 Responses to Commutative Algebra 51

  1. Vanya says:

    In proposition are the maps $\latex \phi_i : M_i \to N_i$ instead of \phi_i : N_i \to M_i?

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s